MHonArc test archive

[Date Prev][Date Next][Thread Prev][Thread Next][Date Index][Thread Index]

Re: diferenta de capital/luxul



Stefan, eu nu spun ca o critica morala a nevoilor ar fi compatibila cu ceea ce astazi este predicat ca liberalism sau libertarianism (si, daca intelegem prin 'liberalism' numai asa ceva, atunci Silviu are dreptate ca 'se' spune numai o parte de adevar, dupa cum si socialismul aplicat astazi in politici peste tot in lume nu prea are legatura cu ce spuneti voi de obicei, tu si Silviu), ci ca o critica morala a nevoilor nu este incompatibila cu propozitiile praxeologiei - care sunt formale si instrumentale, nu presupun neaparat un 'continut' anume al nevoilor. Am mai spus ca o critica a nevoilor va duce la schimbari - considerate obiectivist - in economie, numai ca nu va fi nici o problema cu privire la gradul de satisfactie al consumatorilor daca acestia internalizeaza critica respectiva (sunt fiinte autonome intr-un mai mare grad). Am mai sugerat ca o critica absoluta - mai bine zis, completa - a nevoilor nu este posibila, deci nu vad nici o dificultate legata de prima fraza subliniata de tine mai jos.
    Il citezi pe Mises, in pasajul de mai jos, foarte bine in sprijinul afirmatiilor tale, dar nu neaparat impotriva alor mele, fiindca nu sunt neaparat de acord cu tot ce spune Mises. Eu iau ca centrala teza subiectivitatii economice pentru ca mi se pare relevanta nu numai politic si economic, ci, extrem de important, moral - este implicata autonomia vointei. Falsul principiu moral al heteronomiei vointei este de asemenea vizibil aici: nu sunt liber (pozitiv) pentru ca imi vad nevoile ca obiective - vorba lui Platon, 'oameni care nu cred decat ce pot tine in maini'... (Astfel, propozitiile praxeologiei, bazate pe asa ceva, nu intra in contradictie cu o critica morala a nevoilor. Nu spun ca, in alt sens, a vorbi despre nevoi in sens obiectiv - anume cand vedem bine ca altcineva se concepe 'sub' nevoi - nu este ok. Dar asta este o dicutie pe care am sugerat-o undeva, fara sa fi fost pana acum atinsa.)  
    Acum, ce mi se pare nasol in ce spune Mises mai jos, nu este ce ai subliniat tu, ci asta: "Many foolish things have been said and written about luxury. Against luxury consumption it has been objected that it is unjust that some should enjoy great abundance while others are in want. This argument seems to have some merit. But it only seems so. For if it can be shown that luxury consumption performs a useful function in the system of social cooperation, then the argument will be proved invalid. This, however, is what we shall seek to demonstrate." Vorbeste ca si cum singurul lucru care ar putea legitima statutul luxului ar fi functia economica. Dar chiar economia in cadrul careia luxul poate fi legitimat ca functie nu este posibila in absenta culturii libertatii (lucru cu care este de acord si CC, cu toate ca el tinde sa minimizeze conditia asta culturala). Ca luxul de astazi este nevoia de maine (subiectivism) este o descriere a ceea ce se intampla in momentul de fata, nu decide ce anume trebuie sa fie. Subiectivitatea valorii economice exprimata prin relativism lux/nevoie poate fi pusa si asa: lux, nevoie sunt relative, deci NU este necesar ca ceea este astazi lux sa devina maine nevoie - depinde de cum se privesc oamenii la un moment dat pe ei si cum inteleg fluxul cultural-istoric care a creeat iluzia ca bunul X este necesar ("dar, uite, acum un secol asta era lux, iar acum doua secole, oamenii nici nu aveau asa ceva!"). Si pana aici, repet, inca nu a avut loc o reflectie asupra a ce trebuie sa fie.
    La observatia ta din celalalt mesaj, cred ca raspunsesem deja (autocitat):
"Un alt lucru neclar in ce spusesem anterior este ca am lasat sa se
inteleaga ca intotdeauna, in cazul CS, saracii vor iesi in pierdere, pentru
ca efectele perturbarii economiei i-ar afecta mai mult decat ar putea ei
beneficia de banii primiti. Nu intotdeauna ar fi asa. Daca, de exemplu,
sumele impozitate ar fi mici (perturbare restransa a economiei), iar numarul
saracilor - de asemenea mic, este de asteptat ca diferenta dintre sumele
primite si cele pierdute prin cresterea generala a preturilor sa le fie
favorabila. Eficienta masurii poate fi insa chestionata in felul indicat mai
sus: altii vor fi afectati negativ. Veti spune, poate: 'da, dar asta este
redistribuirea!'. Diferenta ramane intre CC si CS in modul in care se face
redistribuirea; in CS nimeni nu este intrebat daca vrea ca banii sa le fie
luati si 'donati' saracilor. Veti spune: 'da, dar asta nu priveste eficienta
redistribuirii, noi nu discutam probleme de drept!'. OK, ma limitez atunci
la observatia - o luati cum vreti - ca gradul de satisfactie al
consumatorilor (deci si eficienta economica) pe piata depinde in mod direct
de respectarea drepturilor: nimeni nu va fi satisfacut economic daca ii sunt
incalcate drepturile (prin masuri zise, de cele mai multe ori, cu caracter
economic - socialistii spun de obicei jumatate de adevar sau chiar mai
putin)."
 
Daca faceti in mod corect distinctia intre problema eficientei economice si problema dreptului, atunci trebuie sa sesizati corect si modurile de a vorbi - contextele - in care distinctia asta nu se aplica (de ce facem distinctia asta? care-i intinderea valabilitatii ei?).

 
 
Stefan C  
   
despre diferentele de capital si despre ideea lui Stefan Cojocaru ca putem face o critica morala a consumului de lux pentru a-i ajuta pe altii: extras din Mises - "Liberalism" (sublinierile mele)
As vrea sa mentionez ca eu nu-l gasesc pe Mises tot atat de "dezgustator" ca Silviu, dar il folosesc ca sa il contrazic pe Stefan Cojocaru :-).
 
 
 

1
The Foundations of Liberal Policy

5 The Inequality of Wealth and Income

What is most criticized in our social order is the inequality in the distribution of wealth and income, There are rich and poor; there are very rich and very poor. The way out is not far to seek: the equal distribution of all wealth.

The first objection to this proposal is that it will not help the situation much because those of moderate means far outnumber the rich, so that each individual could expect from such a distribution only a quite insignificant increment in his standard of living. This is certainly correct, but the argument is not complete. Those who advocate equality of income distribution overlook the most important point, namely, that the total available for distribution, the annual product of social labor, is not independent of the manner in which it is divided. The fact that that product today is as great as it is, is not a natural or technological phenomenon independent of all social conditions, but entirely the result of our social institutions. Only because inequality of wealth is possible in our social order, only because it stimulates everyone to produce as much as he can and at the lowest cost, does mankind today have at its disposal the total annual wealth now available for consumption. Were this incentive to be destroyed, productivity would be so greatly reduced that the portion that an equal distribution would allot to each individual would be far less than what even the poorest receives today.

The inequality of income distribution has, however, still a second function quite as important as the one already mentioned: it makes possible the luxury of the rich.

Many foolish things have been said and written about luxury. Against luxury consumption it has been objected that it is unjust that some should enjoy great abundance while others are in want. This argument seems to have some merit. But it only seems so. For if it can be shown that luxury consumption performs a useful function in the system of social cooperation, then the argument will be proved invalid. This, however, is what we shall seek to demonstrate.

Our defense of luxury consumption is not, of course, the argument that one occasionally hears, that is, that it spreads money among the people. If the rich did not indulge themselves in luxuries, it is said, the poor would have no income. This is simply nonsense. For if there were no luxury consumption, the capital and labor that would otherwise have been applied to the production of luxury goods would produce other goods: articles of mass consumption, necessary articles, instead of "superfluous" ones.

To form a correct conception of the social significance of luxury consumption, one must first of all realize that the concept of luxury is an altogether relative one. Luxury consists in a way of living that stands in sharp contrast to that of the great mass of one's contemporaries. The conception of luxury is, therefore, essentially historical. Many things that seem to us necessities today were once considered as luxuries. When, in the Middle Ages, an aristocratic Byzantine lady who had married a Venetian doge made use of a golden implement, which could be called the forerunner of the fork as we know it today, instead of her fingers, in eating her meals, the Venetians looked on this as a godless luxury, and they thought it only just when the lady was stricken with a dreadful disease; this must be, they supposed, the well-merited punishment of God for such unnatural extravagance. Two or three generations ago even in England an indoor bathroom was considered a luxury; today the home of every English worker of the better type contains one. Thirty-five years ago there were no automobiles; twenty years ago the possession of such a vehicle was the sign of a particularly luxurious mode of living; today in the United States even the worker has his Ford. This is the course of economic history. The luxury of today is the necessity of tomorrow. Every advance first comes into being as the luxury of a few rich people, only to become, after a time, the indispensable necessity taken for granted by everyone. Luxury consumption provides industry with the stimulus to discover and introduce new, things. It is one of the dynamic factors in our economy. To it we owe the progressive innovations by which the standard of living of all strata of the population has been gradually raised.

Most of us have no sympathy with the rich idler who spends his life in pleasure without ever doing any work. But even he fulfills a function in the life of the social organism. He sets an example of luxury that awakens in the multitude a consciousness of new needs and gives industry the incentive to fulfill them. There was a time when only the rich could afford the luxury of visiting foreign countries. Schiller never saw the Swiss mountains, which he celebrated in Wilhelm Tell, although they bordered on his Swabian homeland. Goethe saw neither Paris nor Vienna nor London. Today, however, hundreds of thousands travel, and soon millions will do so.